International Journal of Fuzzy Logic and Intelligent Systems 2020; 20(1): 77-86
Published online March 25, 2020
https://doi.org/10.5391/IJFIS.2020.20.1.77
© The Korean Institute of Intelligent Systems
Ahmed Abd El-Monsef Allam1, Ahmed Mohammed Zahran2, Ahmed Khalf Mousa2;3, and Hana Mohsen Binshahnah4
1Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science, Assiut University, Assiut, Egypt
2Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science, Al-Azhar University, Assiut, Egypt
3Department of Mathematics, University of Tabuk at Al-Wajh, Saudi Arabia
4Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science, Hadhramout University, Republic of Yemen
Correspondence to :
Ahmed Khalf Mousa (akmousa@azhar.edu.eg)
This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Non-Commercial License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/3.0/) which permits unrestricted noncommercial use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
In present paper, we introduce and study the concepts of
Keywords: Fuzzifying topology, Fuzzifying bitopological space, Separation axioms
In 1963, Kelley [1] introduced the notions of bitopological spaces. Such spaces equipped with its two (arbitrary) topologies. In 1991–1993, Ying [2–4] introduced the concept of the fuzzifying topology with the sematic method of continuous valued logic. On the framework of fuzzifying topology, Shen [5] introduced and studied the notions of separation axioms. In 2003, Zhang and Liu [6] studied the concepts of fuzzy
The contains of this paper are arranged as follows. In Section 3,, we introduce
Firstly, we display the fuzzy logical and corresponding set-theoretical notations used in this paper. For formula
(1)
(2) If , where
is the family of fuzzy sets of
(3) If
In addition, the following derived formulae are given:
(1) [¬
(2) [
(3) [
(4) [
(5) [
(6) [∃
(7) If , then
(a)
(b) [
Secondly, we give the following definitions which are used in the sequel.
Let satisfy the following conditions:
(1)
(2) for any
(3) for any {
Then
Let (
(1) The family of all fuzzifying closed sets is denoted by , and defined as follows:
(2) The neighborhood system of and defined as follows:
(3) The closure
Let (
(1) A unary fuzzy predicate , called fuzzy continuity, is given as follows:
(2) A unary fuzzy predicate , called fuzzy openness, is given as follows:
Let (
Let (
For any
Let (
(1) A set
(2) A set , i.e.,
Let (
,
Let (
(1) ,
(2) ⊨ ℱ
(1) ,
(2) It is similar to (1) above.
For simplicity we put the following notations:
where
Let Ω be the class of all fuzzifying bitopological spaces. The unary fuzzy predicates
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
Let Ω be the class of all fuzzifying bitopological spaces. The unary fuzzy predicates
(1)
(2)
(3)
The following example shows that generally
Let
Note that
Then we have
Let Ω be the class of all fuzzifying bitopological spaces. The unary fuzzy predicates
(1)
(2)
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
The proof is obvious.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
From Lemma 3.3, it is clear.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
From Lemma 2.1, Lemma 3.3 and Theorem 3.1, the proof becomes obvious.
Let (
The proof is obvious.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(1)
(2) It is similar to (1) above.
The following examples show that generally the reverse of Theorem 3.4 need not be true.
Let
Note that
Note that
Let
Note that
Note that
Let (
For any
By the same way, we have
So
On the other hand, from Theorem 3.4 we have
Therefore,
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
(6)
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
It is similar to proof of Theorem 2.6 in [5].
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
Then
(1)
(2) and (3) are similar to that of Theorem 3.6.
Now we define a new weaker form of pairwise normality in the fuzzifying bitopological spaces.
Let Ω be the class of all fuzzifying bitopological spaces. The unary fuzzy predicates
Let (
It is obtained from part (2) of Lemma 3.2.
The following example shows that generally the reverse of Theorem 3.8 need not be true.
Let
Note that
and
Then we have
Let (
(1)
(2)
From Theorem 3.5, the proof becomes obvious.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(1) Since
In fact,
(2) It is similar to (1) above.
From Theorem 4.1 and Theorem 4.2, we have the following result:
Let (
(1)
(2)
The following example shows that generally
For
Let (
(1)
(2) If
(1) It is obtained from part (1) of the Theorem 3.1 and part (2) Theorem 3.2.
(2) Since
Let (
(1)
(2) If
(1) It is obtained from part (3) of the Theorem 3.1 and part (4) of the Theorem 3.2.
(2) It is similar to proof of part (2) of the Theorem 4.3.
In the crisp setting, i.e, if the underlying fuzzifying bitopology is the ordinary bitopology one can have that
(1)
(2)
Generally these statements may not be true in fuzzifying bitopology as illustrated by the following example.
Let
Note that
Let (
(1)
(2) If
(1) It is clear.
(2) It is similar to the proof of part (2) of the Theorem 4.3.
Let (
(1)
(2) If
(1) It is clear.
(2) It is similar to the proof of part (2) of the Theorem 4.3.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
From part (1) of the Theorem 3.1, part (2) of the Theorem 3.2 and part (3) of the Theorem 4.3, the proof becomes obvious.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
(1) From part (1) of the Theorem 3.2 in [8], [
The proof of (2) and (3) is similar to (1) above.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
From part (3) of the Theorem 2.1 in [4] the proof becomes obvious.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(1) (a) Since
(b) Since
From (a) and (b), we have
(2) It is similar to (1) above.
In the present paper we used Łukasiewicz fuzzy logic to extend the notions of separation axioms from the framework of fuzzifying topological spaces into the framework of fuzzifying bitopological spaces and study some relations between them. Also we investigate the image of these kinds of fuzzifying bitopological spaces under some types of fuzzy mappings.
No potential conflict of interest relevant to this article was reported.
E-mail: allam51ahmed@yahoo.com
E-mail: amzahran@azhar.edu.eg
E-mail: akmousa@azhar.edu.eg
E-mail: hmbsh2006@yahoo.com
International Journal of Fuzzy Logic and Intelligent Systems 2020; 20(1): 77-86
Published online March 25, 2020 https://doi.org/10.5391/IJFIS.2020.20.1.77
Copyright © The Korean Institute of Intelligent Systems.
Ahmed Abd El-Monsef Allam1, Ahmed Mohammed Zahran2, Ahmed Khalf Mousa2;3, and Hana Mohsen Binshahnah4
1Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science, Assiut University, Assiut, Egypt
2Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science, Al-Azhar University, Assiut, Egypt
3Department of Mathematics, University of Tabuk at Al-Wajh, Saudi Arabia
4Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science, Hadhramout University, Republic of Yemen
Correspondence to:Ahmed Khalf Mousa (akmousa@azhar.edu.eg)
This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Non-Commercial License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/3.0/) which permits unrestricted noncommercial use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
In present paper, we introduce and study the concepts of
Keywords: Fuzzifying topology, Fuzzifying bitopological space, Separation axioms
In 1963, Kelley [1] introduced the notions of bitopological spaces. Such spaces equipped with its two (arbitrary) topologies. In 1991–1993, Ying [2–4] introduced the concept of the fuzzifying topology with the sematic method of continuous valued logic. On the framework of fuzzifying topology, Shen [5] introduced and studied the notions of separation axioms. In 2003, Zhang and Liu [6] studied the concepts of fuzzy
The contains of this paper are arranged as follows. In Section 3,, we introduce
Firstly, we display the fuzzy logical and corresponding set-theoretical notations used in this paper. For formula
(1)
(2) If , where
is the family of fuzzy sets of
(3) If
In addition, the following derived formulae are given:
(1) [¬
(2) [
(3) [
(4) [
(5) [
(6) [∃
(7) If , then
(a)
(b) [
Secondly, we give the following definitions which are used in the sequel.
Let satisfy the following conditions:
(1)
(2) for any
(3) for any {
Then
Let (
(1) The family of all fuzzifying closed sets is denoted by , and defined as follows:
(2) The neighborhood system of and defined as follows:
(3) The closure
Let (
(1) A unary fuzzy predicate , called fuzzy continuity, is given as follows:
(2) A unary fuzzy predicate , called fuzzy openness, is given as follows:
Let (
Let (
For any
Let (
(1) A set
(2) A set , i.e.,
Let (
,
Let (
(1) ,
(2) ⊨ ℱ
(1) ,
(2) It is similar to (1) above.
For simplicity we put the following notations:
where
Let Ω be the class of all fuzzifying bitopological spaces. The unary fuzzy predicates
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
Let Ω be the class of all fuzzifying bitopological spaces. The unary fuzzy predicates
(1)
(2)
(3)
The following example shows that generally
Let
Note that
Then we have
Let Ω be the class of all fuzzifying bitopological spaces. The unary fuzzy predicates
(1)
(2)
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
The proof is obvious.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
From Lemma 3.3, it is clear.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
From Lemma 2.1, Lemma 3.3 and Theorem 3.1, the proof becomes obvious.
Let (
The proof is obvious.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(1)
(2) It is similar to (1) above.
The following examples show that generally the reverse of Theorem 3.4 need not be true.
Let
Note that
Note that
Let
Note that
Note that
Let (
For any
By the same way, we have
So
On the other hand, from Theorem 3.4 we have
Therefore,
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
(6)
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
It is similar to proof of Theorem 2.6 in [5].
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
Then
(1)
(2) and (3) are similar to that of Theorem 3.6.
Now we define a new weaker form of pairwise normality in the fuzzifying bitopological spaces.
Let Ω be the class of all fuzzifying bitopological spaces. The unary fuzzy predicates
Let (
It is obtained from part (2) of Lemma 3.2.
The following example shows that generally the reverse of Theorem 3.8 need not be true.
Let
Note that
and
Then we have
Let (
(1)
(2)
From Theorem 3.5, the proof becomes obvious.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(1) Since
In fact,
(2) It is similar to (1) above.
From Theorem 4.1 and Theorem 4.2, we have the following result:
Let (
(1)
(2)
The following example shows that generally
For
Let (
(1)
(2) If
(1) It is obtained from part (1) of the Theorem 3.1 and part (2) Theorem 3.2.
(2) Since
Let (
(1)
(2) If
(1) It is obtained from part (3) of the Theorem 3.1 and part (4) of the Theorem 3.2.
(2) It is similar to proof of part (2) of the Theorem 4.3.
In the crisp setting, i.e, if the underlying fuzzifying bitopology is the ordinary bitopology one can have that
(1)
(2)
Generally these statements may not be true in fuzzifying bitopology as illustrated by the following example.
Let
Note that
Let (
(1)
(2) If
(1) It is clear.
(2) It is similar to the proof of part (2) of the Theorem 4.3.
Let (
(1)
(2) If
(1) It is clear.
(2) It is similar to the proof of part (2) of the Theorem 4.3.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
From part (1) of the Theorem 3.1, part (2) of the Theorem 3.2 and part (3) of the Theorem 4.3, the proof becomes obvious.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
(1) From part (1) of the Theorem 3.2 in [8], [
The proof of (2) and (3) is similar to (1) above.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(3)
From part (3) of the Theorem 2.1 in [4] the proof becomes obvious.
Let (
(1)
(2)
(1) (a) Since
(b) Since
From (a) and (b), we have
(2) It is similar to (1) above.
In the present paper we used Łukasiewicz fuzzy logic to extend the notions of separation axioms from the framework of fuzzifying topological spaces into the framework of fuzzifying bitopological spaces and study some relations between them. Also we investigate the image of these kinds of fuzzifying bitopological spaces under some types of fuzzy mappings.
No potential conflict of interest relevant to this article was reported.
A.M. Zahran,O.R. Sayed,M. Azab Abd-Allah,A.K. Mousa
Int. J. Fuzzy Log. Intell. Syst. 2010; 10(4): 296-302 https://doi.org/10.5391/IJFIS.2010.10.4.296